Aristotle h2>
Born: 384 BC in Stagirus, Macedonia, Greece p>
Died: 322 BC in Chalcis, Euboea, Greece p>
Aristotle was not primarily a mathematician but made
important contributions by systematising deductive logic. He wrote on physical
subjects: some parts of his Analytica posteriora show an unusual grasp of the
mathematical method. Primarily, however, he is important in the development of
all knowledge for, as the authors of write: - p>
Aristotle, more than any other thinker, determined the
orientation and the content of Western intellectual history. He was the author
of a philosophical and scientific system that through the centuries became the
support and vehicle for both medieval Christian and Islamic scholastic thought:
until the end of the 17th century, Western culture was Aristotelian. And, even
after the intellectual revolutions of centuries to follow, Aristotelian
concepts and ideas remained embedded in Western thinking. p>
Aristotle was born in Stagirus, or Stagira, or
Stageirus, on the Chalcidic peninsula of northern Greece. His father was
Nicomachus, a medical doctor, while his mother was named Phaestis. Nicomachus
was certainly living in Chalcidice when Aristotle was born and he had probably
been born in that region. Aristotle's mother, Phaestis, came from Chalcis in
Euboea and her family owned property there. p>
There is little doubt that Nicomachus would have
intended Aristotle to become a doctor, for the tradition was that medical
skills were kept secret and handed down from father to son. It was not a
society where people visited a doctor but rather it was the doctors who
travelled round the country tending to the sick. Although we know nothing of
Aristotle's early years it is highly likely that he would have accompanied his
father in his travels. We do know that Nicomachus found the conditions in
Chalcidice less satisfactory than in the neighbouring state of Macedonia and he
began to work there with so much success that he was soon appointed as the
personal physician to Amyntas III, king of Macedonia. p>
There is no record to indicate whether Aristotle lived
with his father in Pella, the capital of Macedonia, while Nicomachus attended
to king Amyntas at the court there. However, Aristotle was certainly friendly
with Philip, king Amyntas's son, some years later and it seems reasonable to
assume that the two, who were almost exactly the same age, had become friendly
in Pella as young children. p>
When Aristotle was about ten years old his father
died. This certainly meant that Aristotle could not now follow in his father's
profession of doctor and, since his mother seems also to have died young,
Aristotle was brought up by a guardian, Proxenus of Atarneus, who was his uncle
(or possibly a family friend as is suggested by some authors). Proxenus taught
Aristotle Greek, rhetoric, and poetry which complemented the biological
teachings that Nicomachus had given Aristotle as part of training his son in medicine.
Since in latter life Aristotle wrote fine Greek prose, this too must have been
part of his early education. p>
In 367 BC Aristotle, at the age of seventeen, became a
student at Plato's Academy in Athens. At the time that Aristotle joined the
Academy it had been operating for twenty years. Plato was not in Athens, but
rather he was on his first visit to Syracuse. We should not think of Plato's
Academy as a non-political organisation only interested in abstract ideas. The
Academy was highly involved in the politics of the time, in fact Plato's visit
to Sicily was for political reasons, and the politics of the Academy and of the
whole region would play a major role in influencing the course of Aristotle's
life. p>
When Aristotle arrived in Athens, the Academy was
being run by Eudoxus of Cnidos in Plato's absence. Speusippus, Plato's nephew,
was also teaching at the Academy as was Xenocrates of Chalcedon. After being a
student, Aristotle soon became a teacher at the Academy and he was to remain
there for twenty years. We know little regarding what Aristotle taught at the
Academy. In [10] Diogenes Laertius, writing in the second century AD, says that
Aristotle taught rhetoric and dialectic. Certainly Aristotle wrote on rhetoric
at this time, issuing Gryllus which attacked the views on rhetoric of
Isocrates, who ran another major educational establishment in Athens. All
Aristotle's writings of this time strongly support Plato's views and those of
the Academy. p>
Towards the end of Aristotle's twenty years at the
Academy his position became difficult due to the political events of the time.
Amyntas, the king of Macedonia, died around 369 BC, a couple of years before
Aristotle went to Athens to join the Academy. Two of Amyntas's sons, Alexander
II and Perdiccas III, each reigned Macedonia for a time but the kingdom
suffered from both internal disputes and external wars. In 359 BC Amyntas's
third son, Philip II came to the throne when Perdiccas was killed fighting off
an Illyrian invasion. Philip used skilful tactics, both military and political,
to allow Macedonia a period of internal peace in which they expanded by
victories over the surrounding areas. p>
Philip captured Olynthus and annexed Chalcidice in 348
BC. Stagirus, the town of Aristotle's birth, held out for a while but was also
defeated by Philip. Athens worried about the powerful threatening forces of
Macedonia, and yet Aristotle had been brought up at the Court of Macedonia and
had probably retained his friendship with Philip. The actual order of events is
now a little uncertain. Plato died in 347 BC and Speusippus assumed the
leadership of the Academy. Aristotle was certainly opposed to the views of
Speusippus and he may have left the Academy following Plato's death for
academic reasons or because he failed to be named head of the Academy himself.
Some sources, however, suggest that he may have left for political reasons
before Plato died because of his unpopularity due to his Macedonian links. p>
Aristotle travelled from Athens to Assos which faces
the island of Lesbos. He was not alone in leaving the Academy for Xenocrates of
Chalcedon left with him. In Assos Aristotle was received by the ruler Hermias
of Atarneus with much acclaim. It is likely that Aristotle was acting as an
ambassador for Philip and he certainly was treated as such by Hermias.
Aristotle married Pythias, the niece and adopted daughter of Hermias, and they
had one child, a daughter also called Pythias. However, Aristotle's wife died
about 10 years after their marriage. It is thought that she was much younger
than Atistotle, being probably of age of about 18 when they married. p>
On Assos, Aristotle became the leader of the group of
philosophers which Hermias had gathered there. It is possible that Xenocrates
was also a member of the group for a time. Aristotle had a strong interest in
anatomy and the structure of living things in general, an interest which his
father had fostered in him in his early years, that helped him to develop a
remarkable talent for observation. Aristotle and the members of his group began
to collect observations while in Assos, in particular in zoology and biology.
Barnes writes in that Aristotle's: - p>
... studies on animals laid the foundations of the
biological sciences; and they were not superseded until more than two thousand
years after his death. The enquiries upon which those great works were based
were probably carried out largely in Assos and Lesbos. p>
Aristotle probably begun his work Politics on Assos as
well as On Kingship which is now lost. He began to develop a philosophy
distinct from that of Plato who had said the kings should be philosophers and
philosophers kings. In On Kingship Aristotle wrote that it is: - p>
... not merely unnecessary for a king to be a
philosopher, but even a disadvantage. Rather a king should take the advice of
true philosophers. Then he would fill his reign with good deeds, not with good
words. p>
However, Aristotle's time in Assos was ended by
political events. The Persians attacked the town and Hermias was captured and
executed. Aristotle escaped and stopped on the island of Lesbos on his way to
Macedonia. It was more than a passing visit for he remained there for about a
year and must have had the group of scientists from Assos with him for they
continued their biological researches there. p>
Macedonia was now at peace with Athens, for Philip had
made a treaty in 346 BC. In 343 BC Aristotle reached the Court of Macedonia and
he was to remain there for seven years. The often quoted story that he became
tutor to the young Alexander the Great, the son of Philip, is almost certainly
a later invention as was pointed out by Jaeger, see. Grayeff in suggests that Philip saw in Aristotle a
future head of the Academy in Athens. Certainly this would have suited Philip well
for Speusippus, the then head of the Academy, was strongly opposed to Philip
and strongly encouraging Athens to oppose the rise of Macedonia. p>
The treaty between Athens and Macedonia began to fall
apart in 340 BC and preparations for war began. The following year Speusippus
died but Aristotle, although proposed as head of the Academy, was not elected.
The position went to Xenocrates and Philip lost interest in his support for
Aristotle. He moved back to his home in Stagirus and took with him to Stagirus
his circle of philosophers and scientists. p>
Aristotle did not marry again after the death of his
wife but he did form a relationship with Herpyllis, who came from his home town
of Stagirus. It is not clear when they first met but together they had a son,
Nicomachus, named after Aristotle's father. p>
Philip was now at the height of his power but, as so
often happens, that proved the time for internal disputes. Aristotle supported
Alexander, Philip's son who soon became king. Alexander decided on a policy
similar to his father in regard to Athens and sought to assert his power by
peaceful means. Alexander protected the Academy and encouraged it to continue
with its work. At the same time, however, he sent Aristotle to Athens to found
a rival establishment. p>
In 335 BC Aristotle founded his own school the Lyceum
in Athens. He arrived in the city with assistants to staff the school and a
large range of teaching materials he had gathered while in Macedonia; books,
maps, and other teaching material which may well have been intended at one
stage to support Aristotle in his bid to become head of the Academy. The
Academy had always been narrow in its interests but the Lyceum under Aristotle
pursued a broader range of subjects. Prominence was given by Aristotle to the
detailed study of nature and in this and all the other subjects he studied: - p>
His own researches were carried out in company, and he
communicated his thoughts to his friends and pupils, never thinking to retain
them as a private treasure-store. He thought, indeed, that a man could not
claim to know a subject unless he was capable of transmitting his knowledge to
others, and he regarded teaching as the proper manifestation of knowledge. p>
Whether the works that come down to us are due to
Aristotle or to later members of his school was questioned by a number of
scholars towards the end of the 19th century. The reasons are discussed by
Jaeger, but in this work Jaeger argues that the apparent differences in the
approach by Aristotle in different works can be explained by his ideas
developing over a number of years. Grayeff [6] examines certain texts in detail
and again claims that they represent developments in the ideas of Aristotle's
school long after his death. He writes: - p>
According to a tradition which arose about two hundred
and fifty years after his death, which then became dominant and even today is
hardly disputed, Aristotle in these same years lecturer - not once, but two or
three times, in almost every subject - on logic, physics, astronomy,
meteorology, zoology, metaphysics, theology, psychology, politics, economics,
ethics, rhetoric, poetics; and that he wrote down these lectures, expanding
them and amending them several times, until they reached the stage in which we
read them. However, still more astounding is the fact that the majority of these
subjects did not exist as such before him, so that he would have been the first
to conceive of and establish them, as systematic disciplines. p>
After the death of Alexander the Great in 323 BC,
anti-Macedonian feeling in Athens made Aristotle retire to Chalcis where he
lived in the house which had once belonged to his mother and was still retained
by the family. He died the following year from a stomach complaint at the age
of 62. p>
It is virtually impossible to give an impression of
Aristotle's personality with any certainty but the authors of write: - p>
The anecdotes related of him reveal him as a kindly,
affectionate character, and they show barely any trace of the self-importance
that some scholars think they can detect in his works. His will, which has been
preserved, exhibits the same kindly traits; he makes references to his happy
family life and takes solicitous care of his children, as well as his servants.
p>
Barnes writes: - p>
He was a bit of a dandy, wearing rings on his fingers
and cutting his hair fashionably short. He suffered from poor digestion, and is
said to have been spindle-shanked. He was a good speaker, lucid in his
lectures, persuasive in conversation; and he had a mordant wit. His enemies,
who were numerous, made him out to be arrogant and overbearing. ... As a man he
was, I suspect, admirable rather than amiable. p>
We have commented above on the disputes among modern
scholars as to whether Aristotle wrote the treatises now assigned to him. We do
know that his work falls into two distinct parts, namely works which he
published during his lifetime and are now lost (although some fragments survive
in quotations in works by others), and the collection of writings which have
come down to us and were not published by Aristotle in his lifetime. We can say
with certainty that Aristotle never intended these 30 works which fill over
2000 printed pages to be published. They are certainly lecture notes from the
courses given at the Lyceum either being, as most scholars believe, the work of
Aristotle, or of later lecturers. Of course it is distinctly possible that they
are notes of courses originally given by Aristotle but later added to by other
lecturers after Aristotle's death. p>
The works were first published in about 60 BC by
Andronicus of Rhodes, the last head of the Lyceum. Certainly: - p>
The form, titles, and order of Aristotle's texts that
are studied today were given to them by Andronicus almost three centuries after
the philosopher's death, and the long history of commentary upon them began at
this stage. p>
What do these works contain? There are important works
on logic. Aristotle believed that logic was not a science but rather had to be
treated before the study of every branch of knowledge. Aristotle's name for
logic was "analytics", the term logic being introduced by Xenocrates
working at the Academy. Aristotle believed that logic must be applied to the
sciences: - p>
The sciences - at any rate the theoretical sciences --
are to be axiomatised. What, then, are their axioms to be? What conditions must
a proposition satisfy to count as an axiom? again, what form will the
derivations within each science take? By what rules will theorems be deduced
from axioms? Those are among the questions which Aristotle poses in his logical
writings, and in particular in the works known as Prior and Posterior
Analytics. p>
In fact in Prior Analytics Aristotle proposed the now
famous Aristotelian syllogistic, a form of argument consisting of two premises
and a conclusion. His example is: - p>
(i) Every Greek is a person. p>
(ii) Every person is mortal. p>
(iii) Every Greek is mortal. p>
Aristotle was not the first to suggest axiom systems.
Plato had made the bold suggestion that there might be a single axiom system to
embrace all knowledge. Aristotle went for the somewhat more possible suggestion
of an axiom system for each science. Notice that Euclid and his axiom system
for geometry came after Aristotle. p>
Another topic to which Aristotle made major
contributions was natural philosophy or rather physics by today's terminology.
(I [EFR] show my age and the traditional nature of St Andrews University if I
remark that in the 1960s a pass in 'General Natural Philosophy' formed part of
my degree.) Aristotle looks at matter, change, movement, space, position, and
time. He also made contributions to the study of astronomy where in particular
he studied comets, geography with an examination of features such as rivers),
chemistry where he was interested in processes such as burning, as well as
meteorology and the study of rainbows. p>
As well as important works on zoology and psychology,
Aristotle wrote his famous work on metaphysics. This, according to Aristotle,
studies: - p>
... the most general or abstract features of reality
and the principles that have universal validity. ... metaphysics studies
whatever must be true of all existent things just insofar as they exist, [and]
it studies the general conditions which any existing thing must satisfy. p>
Although Aristotle does not appear to have made any
new discoveries in mathematics, he is important in the development of
mathematics. As Heath explains in: - p>
The importance of a proper understanding of the
mathematics in Aristotle lies principally in the fact that most of his
illustrations of scientific method are taken from mathematics. p>
Clearly Aristotle had a thorough grasp of elementary
mathematics and believed mathematics to have great importance as one of three
theoretical sciences. However, it is fair to say that he did not agree with
Plato, who elevated mathematics to such a prominent place of study that there
was little room for the range of sciences studied by Aristotle. The other two
theoretical sciences, Aristotle claimed, were (using modern terminology)
philosophy and theoretical physics. p>
Heath notes in
the introduction to some of the
mathematics referred to by Aristotle in his works: - p>
... Aristotle was aware of the important discoveries
of Eudoxus which affected profoundly the exposition of the Elements by Euclid.
One allusion clearly shows that Aristotle knew of Eudoxus's great Theory of
Proportion which was expounded by Euclid in his Book V, and recognised the
importance of it. Another passage recalls the fundamental assumption on which
Eudoxus based his 'method of exhaustion' for measuring areas and volumes; and,
of course, Aristotle was familiar with the system of concentric spheres by
which Eudoxus and Callippus accounted theoretically for the independent motions
of the sun, moon, and planets. ... p>
The incommensurable is mentioned over and over again,
but the case mentioned is that of the diagonal of a square in relation to its
side; there is no allusion to the extension of the theory to other cases by
Theodorus and Theaetetus ... p>
Heath also mentions the mathematics which
Aristotle, perhaps surprising, does not refer to. There is: - p>
... no allusion to conic sections, to the doubling of
the cube, or to the trisection of an angle. The problem of squaring the circle
is mentioned in connection with the attempts of Antiphon, Bryson, and
Hippocrates to solve it; but there is nothing about the curve of Hippias ... p>
While Heath
discusses the many mathematical references in Aristotle, the book
attempts to construct (or reconstruct) a work on Aristotle's view of the
philosophy of mathematics. As Apostle writes in: - p>
... numerous passages on mathematics are distributed
throughout the works we possess and indicate a definite philosophy of
mathematics, so that an attempt to construct or reconstruct that philosophy
with a fairly high degree of accuracy is possible. p>
We end our discussion with an illustration of
Aristotle's ideas of 'continuous' and 'infinite' in mathematics. Heath explains Aristotle's idea that
'continuous': - p>
... could not be made up of indivisible parts; the
continuous is that in which the boundary or limit between two consecutive
parts, where they touch, is one and the same ... p>
As to the infinite Aristotle believed that it did not
actually exist but only potentially exists. Aristotle writes in Physics (see
for example): - p>
But my argument does not anyhow rob mathematicians of
their study, although it denies the existence of the infinite in the sense of
actual existence as something increased to such an extent that it cannot be
gone through; for, as it is, they do not need the infinite or use it, but only
require that the finite straight line shall be as long as they please. ...
Hence it will make no difference to them for the purpose of proofs. p>
J J O'Connor and E F Robertson p>
Список
літератури h2>
Для підготовки
даної роботи були використані матеріали з сайту http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/
p>